{"id":15184,"date":"2021-01-28T10:21:26","date_gmt":"2021-01-28T10:21:26","guid":{"rendered":"https:\/\/blogs.lse.ac.uk\/humanrights\/?p=2371"},"modified":"2021-01-28T10:21:26","modified_gmt":"2021-01-28T10:21:26","slug":"is-the-criminalisation-of-migration-racist","status":"publish","type":"post","link":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/2021\/01\/28\/is-the-criminalisation-of-migration-racist\/","title":{"rendered":"Is the Criminalisation of Migration Racist?"},"content":{"rendered":"

The death of four Iranian migrants – including two children aged just five and eight – in the English Channel in October 2020, offers a confined illustration of what has become a harrowingly common scene across European borders, but one that is met with an increasingly insouciant citizenry (Guardian, 2020a; Guardian, 2020b). Indeed, the systematic nature by which Europe has ostracised non-white, undocumented migrants and exposed those already fleeing war to further fatal risk, shows a chilling disregard for human dignity and fits comfortably within Gilmore\u2019s definition of \u2018racism\u2019 as \u2018the state sanctioned or extra-legal production and exploitation of group-differentiated vulnerability to premature death\u2019 (2002: 261).<\/p>\n

The study of postcolonial racism must address its foundational structural apparatus. Specifically, exclusion is facilitated by the nation-state paradigm at the crux of international law. The \u2018inalienability\u2019 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) presents humanity itself as a source of law; however, within the international legal system, the nation-state recognises no superior authority. Thus, there remains no rights anterior to the political will of a distinct nation-state (Bentham, 1843). It is through the process of naturalisation that an individual obtains their humanity and rights, asserting \u2018[w]e are not born equal, we become equal as members of a group on the strength of our decision to guarantee ourselves mutually equal rights\u2019 (Arendt, 1949: 33).<\/p>\n

Perhaps paradoxically amidst the forces of neoliberal globalisation, the modern nation-state is increasingly marked by borders attempting to distinguish those who belong and those who do not. Indeed, the intercourse between the global and the familiar has generated an insecurity of identity, diminishing both state sovereignty, and strained welfare resources (Pickering et al, 2014: 388). Such trepidation is projected onto the precarious figure of the \u2018undocumented migrant\u2019 who offers the \u2018fullest and most tangible embodiment of \u2018otherness\u2019\u2019 (Bauman, 2000: 108-9).<\/p>\n

The \u2018War on Terror\u2019 has exacerbated this fear of outsiders through its central tenet of an \u2018enemy within\u2019. Ironically, the gruesome November Paris attacks in 2015 were perpetrated by (racialised minority) European citizens; yet, the insidious spectre of Europe\u2019s \u2018homegrown\u2019, \u2018Islamic terrorist\u2019 is \u2018routinely racialized as being \u2018of migrant background\u2019\u2019 (de Genova, 2018: 1773), as crudely observable within mainstream media.<\/p>\n

The concomitant resurgence of neo-nationalism across Europe (Bjorgo and White, 1993) has seen political leaders promise strong migration control. Amidst a growing disconnect between politicians and electorate, responding to (mis)conceptions of migration is one of the few jobs governments \u2018can do and be seen doing\u2019 (Bauman, 2000: 108-9).<\/p>\n

Politicians utilise the \u2018deviant immigrant\u2019 construction to justify a repressive national-security (as opposed to human rights) centred approach to immigration. This has informed the development of \u2018crimmigration law\u2019 (Stumpf, 2006), a phrase that depicts the process of \u2018making people illegal\u2019 through the contemporary convergence of immigration law and the criminal justice system (Dauvergne, 2008). The two operate as \u2018gatekeepers of membership\u2019 within the nation-state (Stumpf, 2006). Such pre-emptive security necessarily encompasses identifying a \u2018suspect\u2019 community. Nationality is a significant distinguishing factor which \u2018is tied up with visible difference and [thus] people of colour tend to be targets for surveillance and control\u2019 (Bowling, 2020: 165). The economically and culturally (or, rather, racially) undesirable migrants generally hail from formerly colonised countries. They are posited as inherently unlike \u2018us\u2019, and thus undeserving of our solidarity or even the succour of our penal welfare system (Aas, 2007: 80). Their movement is illegalised and met with hard borders.<\/p>\n

Take the example of the UK government who proudly note how all violations of immigration law now constitute criminal offences (Home Office, 2010: 26). Individuals from Africa, and most of Asia and South America, require visas to enter the EU. The vast majority of applicants, particularly the most vulnerable, cannot satisfy this threshold, and are thus forced to first arrive in Europe illegally before pursuing an asylum claim. Within the UK, entering without documents (previously an administrative violation) is now a strict liability offence and the most prosecuted immigration offence (Aliverti, 2012: 103). Consequently, \u2018illegal\u2019 foreign nationals occupy an expanding proportion of the UK\u2019s prison population where, contrary to citizen inmates, imprisonment is not geared towards rehabilitation and reintegration into the social, but deportation (Kaufman, 2013).<\/p>\n

Furthermore, \u2018administrative\u2019 responses to immigration offences progressively imitate criminal ones. Administrative detention facilities have been erected in great numbers across the Western world, constituting \u2018heavily racialized sites of confinement, populated almost entirely by citizens from the global south\u2019 (Bosworth et al, 2016: 221). Moreover, living conditions in many detention facilities are actually worse than prisons and, unsurprisingly, mental and physical health problems are rife amongst the incarcerated (Bosworth, 2012: 129). Such is compounded by the fact that the majority of detainees have not been criminally convicted but are being held (sometimes indefinitely) on the basis of security concerns, thus not meeting the constitutional protections enjoyed by citizens.<\/p>\n

Such differential treatment is legitimised by democracy\u2019s distinction between those deserving of the benefits of inclusion, a \u2018citizen\u2019, and those undeserving, a \u2018non-citizen\u2019. Classification is depersonalising; \u2018non-citizens\u2019 are viewed as dangerous due to arbitrary factors like race and nationality, divorced from their individuality and intrinsic human dignity (of which Western actors are paradoxically the greatest (rhetorical) champion thereof). Inevitably, innocent persons are labelled \u2018risky\u2019 and subjected to intrusive measures on account of possessing features of a \u2018typical terrorist\u2019 (Mythen and Walkate, 2006). Through this process of \u2018dehumanisation\u2019, the undocumented migrant\u2019s morality is concealed, facilitating violence and exclusion.<\/p>\n

This is at the heart of the callous lack of political succour. Note the contradictory attitudes towards the macabre spectacles of parents desperately acting in their family\u2019s best interests fleeing the horrific violence of the Middle East (where Western foreign policy is embroiled) and the political sympathy for the Prime Minister\u2019s old chum when he allegedly breaks COVID restrictions (Guardian, 2020c). Of these fleeing refugees, at least 3,700 drowned in 2015 alone (Anderson, 2017: 1527). Despite many looking to Europe for hope, the treacherous journey does not end once inside Europe\u2019s borders. Amidst, those walking along Eastern Europe\u2019s motorways was a European flag with the message \u2018We share your respect for justice, freedom and human rights and here we are! We belong!\u2019 (ibid: 1528). However, when outsiders invoke human rights, it draws many similarities to that of the discourse of societies for the prevention of animal cruelty, \u2018[asserting a] belonging to the human race in the same way that an animal belongs to animal species [with the chilling possibility] that they might end by being considered beasts\u2019 (Arendt, 1951: 297).<\/p>\n

When one considers the magnitude of fatalities upon Europe\u2019s shores; the indeterminate detention and public degradation of deportation; and the denial of access to a welfare system funded by the spoils of colonialism (Drayton, 2012: 162), it is easy to assume that undocumented migrants have their human rights violated. However, as with the plight of the stateless post-world war (Arendt 1949: 31), these individuals do not have their human rights violated; rather, they have no human rights because they are not considered human equals. Their exclusion from human political community reduces them to \u2018bare life\u2019 (Agamben, 1998), where \u2018all that remains is their total subjection to sovereign power\u2019 (Barker, 2013: 241).<\/p>\n

It is thus the (re)discovery of our collective humanity, and the revitalisation of a morally engaged public space capable of challenging narratives of fear, which offers the true antidote to the contemporary \u2018migrant crisis\u2019. Yet, the task is tremendous, and optimism is deferred. Indeed, Europe\u2019s exclusionary borders, through systematically blocking access and safe passage, expose almost entirely non-white migrants to fatal risk. In this, Gilmore\u2019s definition of \u2018racism\u2019 become salient and damning.<\/p>\n

 <\/p>\n

References<\/strong>
\nAas, KF. (2007). Globalization and Crime. London: Sage.<\/p>\n

Agamben, G. (1998). Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.<\/p>\n

Aliverti, A. (2012). Making Home Safe? The Role of Criminal Law and Punishment in British Immigration Controls. DPhil Thesis, University of Oxford.<\/p>\n

Anderson, B. (2017). Towards a New Politics of Migration? Ethnic and Racial Studies, 40(9), 1527.<\/span><\/p>\n

Arendt, H. (1951). The Origins of Totalitarianism. London: Martin Secker & Warburg.<\/p>\n

Arendt, H. (1949). \u2018The Rights of Man\u2019: What Are They? Modern Review, 3(1), 24.<\/p>\n

Barker, V. (2013). Democracy and Deportation: Why Membership Matters Most. In: M Bosworth & K Aas, eds., Migration and Punishment: Citizenship, Crime Control and Social Exclusion, Oxford: Oxford University Press.<\/p>\n

Bauman, Z. (2000). Liquid Modernity. Cambridge: Polity.<\/p>\n

Bentham, J. (1843). \u2018Anarchical Fallacies\u2019 in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, published under the Superintendence of his Executor, John Bowring. Edinburgh: William Tait.<\/p>\n

Bjorgo, T & White, R. (1993). Racist Violence in Europe. Basingstoke: Macmillan.<\/p>\n

Bosworth, M. (2012). Subjectivity and Identity in Detention: Punishment and Society in a Global Age. Theoretical Criminology, 16(2), 123.<\/p>\n

Bosworth, M, Hoyle, C & Zedner, L. (2016). The Changing Contours of Criminal Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.<\/p>\n

Bowling, B. (2020). \u2018A really hostile environment\u2019: Adiaphorization,Global Policing and the Crimmigration Control System. Theoretical Criminology, 24(2), 163.\u00a0<\/span><\/p>\n

Dauvergne, C. (2008). Making People Illegal. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<\/p>\n

De Genova, N. (2018) The \u201cmigrant crisis\u201d as racial crisis: do Black Lives Matter in Europe? Ethnic and Racial Studies, 41(10), 1765.<\/p>\n

Drayton, R. (2012). Imperial History and the Human Future. History Workshop Journal, 74(1), 156.<\/p>\n

Gilmore, RW. (2002). Race and Globalization. In: R Johnston, P Taylor & M Watts, eds., Geographies of Global Change: Remapping the World, Malden, MA: Blackwell.<\/p>\n

Grierson, J. (2020a). Four dead including two children after migrant boat sinks in Channel. Guardian. Available at:\u00a0https:\/\/www.theguardian.com\/world\/2020\/oct\/27\/eighteen-people-in-hospital-as-migrant-boat-sinks-off-french-coast<\/a> [accessed 10 December 2020].<\/p>\n

Home Office. (2010). Protecting our border, protecting the public. The UK Border Agency\u2019s five year strategy for enforcing our immigration rules and addressing immigration and cross border crime. London: Home Office.<\/p>\n

Kaufman, E. (2013). Hubs and Spokes: The Transformation of the British Prison. In: K Aas & M Bosworth, eds., Migration and Punishment: Citizenship, Crime Control and Social Exclusion, Oxford: Oxford University Press.<\/p>\n

MacInnes, P. (2020c). Cummings and cabinet cheerleaders feel heat from social media fury. Guardian. Available at: https:\/\/www.theguardian.com\/politics\/2020\/may\/23\/cummings-and-cabinet-cheerleaders-feel-heat-from-social-media-fury<\/a> [accessed 10 December 2020].<\/p>\n

Mythen, G. & Walkate, S. (2006b). Criminology and Terrorism: Which Thesis? British Journal of Criminology, 46(3), 379.<\/p>\n

Pickering, S, Bosworth, M, & Aas, KF. (2014). The Criminology of Mobility. In: S Pickering & J Ham, eds., The Routledge Handbook on Crime and International Migration, London: Routledge.<\/p>\n

Stumpf, J. (2006). The Crimmigration Crisis: Immigrants, Crime and Sovereign Power. Bepress Legal Series, Working Paper 1635. Available at: https:\/\/ www.law.bepress.com\/expresso\/eps\/1635<\/a> [accessed 10 December 2020].<\/p>\n

Tondo, L. (2020b). More than 110 migrants die in Mediterranean in three days. Guardian. Available at:\u00a0https:\/\/www.theguardian.com\/world\/2020\/nov\/12\/bodies-of-74-migrants-wash-up-on-libyan-beach<\/a>\u00a0[accessed 10 December 2020].<\/p>\n\n

This post was originally published on LSE Human Rights<\/a>. <\/p>","protected":false},"excerpt":{"rendered":"

The death of four Iranian migrants \u2013 including two children aged just five and eight \u2013 in the English Channel in October 2020, offers a confined illustration of what has become a harrowingly common scene across European borders, but one that is met with an increasingly insouciant citizenry (Guardian, 2020a; Guardian, 2020b). Indeed, the systematic \u2026 Continued<\/a><\/p>\n","protected":false},"author":439,"featured_media":0,"comment_status":"closed","ping_status":"closed","sticky":false,"template":"","format":"standard","meta":{"footnotes":""},"categories":[879,3287,242],"tags":[],"_links":{"self":[{"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/15184"}],"collection":[{"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts"}],"about":[{"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/types\/post"}],"author":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/users\/439"}],"replies":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/comments?post=15184"}],"version-history":[{"count":1,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/15184\/revisions"}],"predecessor-version":[{"id":15185,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/15184\/revisions\/15185"}],"wp:attachment":[{"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/media?parent=15184"}],"wp:term":[{"taxonomy":"category","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/categories?post=15184"},{"taxonomy":"post_tag","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/tags?post=15184"}],"curies":[{"name":"wp","href":"https:\/\/api.w.org\/{rel}","templated":true}]}}