{"id":679332,"date":"2022-05-31T14:39:38","date_gmt":"2022-05-31T14:39:38","guid":{"rendered":"https:\/\/dissidentvoice.org\/?p=130043"},"modified":"2022-05-31T14:39:38","modified_gmt":"2022-05-31T14:39:38","slug":"common-sense-in-the-form-of-theory","status":"publish","type":"post","link":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/2022\/05\/31\/common-sense-in-the-form-of-theory\/","title":{"rendered":"Common Sense in the Form of Theory"},"content":{"rendered":"

\"\"<\/a>In the ideological disciplines\u2014the humanities and social sciences\u2014it is rare to come across a theoretical work that doesn\u2019t seem to fetishize verbiage and jargonizing for their own sake. From the relatively lucid analytical Marxism of an Erik Olin Wright1<\/a><\/sup> to the turgid cultural theory of a Stuart Hall, pretentious prolixity is, apparently, seen as an end in itself. In such an academic context, one of the highest services an intellectual can perform is simply to return to the basics of theoretic common sense, stated clearly and concisely. Society is very complex, but, as Noam Chomsky likes to say, insofar as we understand it at all, our understanding can in principle be expressed rather simply and straightforwardly. Not only is such expression more democratic and accessible, thus permitting a broader diffusion of critical understanding of the world; it also has the merit of showing that, once you shed the paraphernalia of most academic writing, nothing particularly profound is being said. Vivek Chibber\u2019s The Class Matrix: Social Theory after the Cultural Turn<\/a><\/em> (Harvard University Press, 2022) constitutes an exemplary demonstration of this fact, and of these virtues.<\/p>\n

Chibber has been waging a war against postmodern theory for some time now, ably defending Marxian common sense against generations of carping \u201cculturalist\u201d critics. His Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital<\/i> (2013) brilliantly showed that the Marxian \u201cmetanarrative\u201d that has come under sustained attack by poststructuralists and postmodernists retains its value as an explanation of the modern world, and that many of the (often highly obscure) alternative conceptualizations of postcolonial theorists are deeply flawed. More recently, in an article published in 2020 in the journal Catalyst <\/i>(\u201cOrientalism and Its Afterlives<\/a>\u201d), Chibber has persuasively criticized Edward Said\u2019s classic Orientalism <\/i>for its idealistic interpretation of modern imperialism as emanating in large part from an age-old European Orientalist discourse, rather than from a capitalist political economy that\u2014as materialists argue\u2014merely used such a discourse to rationalize its global expansion. In more popular venues too, notably Jacobin<\/i>, Chibber has argued for the centrality of materialism to the projects of both interpreting and changing the world.<\/p>\n

The Class Matrix <\/i>continues his engagement with these issues, this time in the form of a systematic critique of cultural theory, specifically of its inability to explain the sources of stability and conflict in modern society. Materialism, in contrast\u2014i.e., a primary emphasis on such concepts as class structures and objective economic interests rather than \u201cdiscourses,\u201d \u201ccultures,\u201d \u201cidentities,\u201d and \u201cmeanings\u201d\u2014is quite capable of explaining society, and can rather easily be defended against the criticisms of (some) culturalists. The book\u2019s admirable lucidity serves several functions: first, Chibber is able to present the arguments of a variety of \u201cculturalisms,\u201d from Gramscians\u2019 to the Frankfurt School\u2019s to those of the post-1970s cultural turn, very clearly and in a way that illuminates the stakes of the debate; second, his eloquent reconstruction of (aspects of) cultural theory lays the ground for an equally eloquent, and much more thorough, exposition of structural class theory, which is shown to have no difficulty (contrary to the claims of culturalists) in explaining the longevity and stability of capitalism; third, the discarding of all unnecessary verbiage and jargon makes it clear just how intellectually trivial these long-running \u201ctheoretical\u201d debates are in the first place. One can have a perfectly defensible and sophisticated understanding of the modern world on the basis of a little critical common sense and knowledge of history.<\/p>\n

Chibber starts by presenting the culturalist case. Why didn\u2019t the West become socialist in the twentieth century, as Marxists predicted? Evidently Marx had gotten something wrong. In fact, it was argued (in the postwar era), he neglected the role of culture <\/i>in forming the consciousness of the working class. Mass culture and the diffusion of dominant ideologies were able to reconcile the working class to capitalism, indeed to generate active popular consent for it. This analysis amounted to a demotion of the classical Marxist emphasis on the conflictual dynamics of the class structure\u2014which supposedly would naturally lead to proletarian class consciousness and thereby revolution\u2014in favor of the cohesive functions of mid-twentieth-century culture. Later culturalists took this argument a step further by rejecting the Marxian theory altogether, arguing that culture is actually prior<\/i> to structure: what people are really presented with are not unmediated structures or objective material interests but \u201cconstellations of meaning\u201d (p. 6), social identities, local cultures, contingent processes of socialization that shape how actors understand the many structures they are located in. One cannot (pace<\/i> classical Marxism) predict behavior from people\u2019s structural locations and the interests they supposedly define, because people first have to interpret<\/i> structures, a process that is highly contingent and variable. Subjectivity, therefore, is primary, and the objectivity of class structures tends to evaporate.<\/p>\n

Chibber\u2019s response to this postmodernist argument, in effect, is that while it is perfectly true every structure is steeped in culture and agents\u2019 subjectivity, this hardly implies the causal inertness of class location. Capitalist institutions don\u2019t exactly impose high interpretive requirements: everyone is capable of understanding \u201cwhat it means\u201d to be a worker or a capitalist. If you lack ownership of the means of production, you either submit to wage labor or you starve. The economic structures force themselves on you. \u201c[T]he proletarian\u2019s meaning orientation <\/i>is [therefore] the effect of his structural location<\/i>\u201d (p. 34). Similarly, the capitalist has to obey market pressures (structures) in order to survive as a capitalist, so he, too, is compelled to subordinate his normative orientation to objectively existing capitalist institutions. In fact, it is the postmodern culturalists who are in the weaker position: how can they explain \u201cthe indubitable fact of capitalism\u2019s expansion across the globe and the obvious similarity in its macrodynamics across these regions\u201d without accepting materialist assumptions (p. 45)?<\/p>\n

Having dispatched this particular objection to materialism, Chibber moves on to other difficulties. Given the antagonistic relations between worker and capitalist (which Chibber elaborates on in detail), why hasn\u2019t collective resistance, and ultimately revolution, been more common? The obvious answer, contrary to cultural theory, is that the asymmetry of power between worker and capitalist is so great that workers find it quite difficult to fight successfully for their collective interests. The insecurity of the worker\u2019s position (for example, he can be fired for union activity) makes it easier and safer to pursue individualized <\/i>modes of advancement or resistance. Moreover, the intrinsic problems of collective action\u2014free rider problems, difficulty in securing agreement among large numbers of workers, etc.\u2014militate against class consciousness and collective resistance. Classical Marxists were wrong to assume that the most rational path for workers would always be the \u201ccollective\u201d path. In fact, contingent cultural considerations play an important role in the formation (in any given case) of class consciousness\u2014although culture always remains constrained by material factors.<\/p>\n

Having successfully and eloquently deployed common sense in his first two chapters, Chibber now turns, in the lengthy third chapter, to an explanation of how capitalism has endured. Here, too, he prefers common sense to the idealistic arguments of many Gramscians and New Left theorists, who pointed to bourgeois \u201ccultural hegemony\u201d and ideological indoctrination as having manufactured consent among the working class. One problem with this theory is its dim view of workers: \u201cCulturalists are in the embarrassing position of claiming implicitly that while they <\/i>can discern the exploitative\u2014and hence unjust\u2014character of the employment relation, the actors who are, in fact<\/i>, being exploited, who are experiencing its brute facts, are not capable of doing so\u201d (p. 91). There are, admittedly, other possible understandings of the basis of mass consent, more materialistic understandings, but in the end Chibber rejects these as the primary explanation for capitalist stability. Instead, he argues that workers simply resign <\/i>themselves to capitalism\u2014they \u201caccept their location in the class structure because they see no other viable option\u201d (p. 106). What Marx called \u201cthe dull compulsion of economic relations\u201d keeps the gears of capitalism grinding on, generation after generation, including in the absence of workers\u2019 \u201cconsent\u201d to their subordination.2<\/a><\/sup> In short, the class structure itself\u2014the enormous power asymmetry between employer and employee\u2014underwrites its own stability, and there is no need to invoke \u201cconsent\u201d at all (even if such consent does, perhaps, exist in certain periods).<\/p>\n

There remain a couple of other issues Chibber has to address in order for his defense of materialism to be really systematic. First, what about the old, E. P. Thompsonian charge that \u201cstructural theories bury social agency\u201d (p. 122)? Is this necessarily the case, this conflict between structure and agency? No, as long as one acknowledges the role of reasons<\/i> in motivating people\u2019s actions. \u201cThe structure is not reproduced because it turns agents into automatons but because it generates good reasons <\/i>for them to play by its rules\u201d (p. 123). A structural process may be rather deterministic in its outcome, but it \u201cis generated by the active intervention of social agency\u201d (p. 126). Given the structures of capitalism, people rationally adapt to them, regulating their behavior in accord with them. Structure thus exerts its causal force precisely through agency.<\/p>\n

Of course, agency also exists in tension with structure insofar as agents can flout institutional norms or even rebel against particular structures. This point brings us to another question Chibber considers, namely the relation between structural \u201cdeterminism\u201d and contingency<\/i>, another favorite concept\u2014along with agency\u2014of the postmodern cultural turn. His argument here is quite rich and nuanced, much too subtle, in fact, to be summarized in a short book review. (It goes without saying that I have merely been outlining his arguments, hardly doing justice to their richness.) One might think that such an austere structuralism as Chibber defends would be unable to account for the contingency of social processes, but through a fairly ingenious analysis he is able to answer this objection, too. Even prima facie, however, the objection doesn\u2019t hold much water, because capitalist relations are evidently compatible with an immense variety of social structures, such that between nations and even within a nation there can be great heterogeneity of local cultures. In a world of infinitely many structures and cultures interacting and overlapping, all of them being activated and enlivened by countless individual free wills, there is clearly a place for contingency on both small and large scales. Materialism can therefore accommodate the \u201cargument from contingency.\u201d<\/p>\n

The Class Matrix<\/i>, in short, is a quite thorough and impressive work, not only a compelling defense of materialism but also a fair-minded if highly critical engagement with cultural theory. It isn\u2019t clear how culturalists\u2014especially the anti-Marxist ones\u2014can effectively respond to this broadside, tightly and cogently argued as it is. They might, perhaps, be able to make the case that there is a greater role for culture than Chibber allows (although he does grant the importance of cultural considerations at many points in his arguments), but they certainly can no longer sustain the claim that materialism is deeply flawed.<\/p>\n

In fact, that claim could never have been sustained anyway, because, in the end, materialism\u2014the causal primacy of class structures (and the theoretical implications of this doctrine)\u2014is little more than common sense. The average member of the working class, more insightful (realistic) in many ways than most intellectuals, could tell you about the overwhelming importance of economic institutions. If classical Marxism got certain predictions wrong, that wasn\u2019t because of any inherent flaws in historical materialism; as Chibber shows, it was because the original theorists misunderstood the implications of their own theory. There was never a good reason to think socialist revolution would \u201cnaturally\u201d happen as workers \u201cnaturally\u201d achieved greater class consciousness. These predictions were but a projection of the hopes of Marxists, not logical entailments of materialism. In our own day, when the historic achievements of Western labor movements have been or are in the process of being destroyed, it is unclear what the way forward is\u2014except, as ever, for working-class self-organization and critical materialist understanding of society. Toward the latter task, at least, The Class Matrix <\/i>makes a valuable contribution.<\/p>\n

\"\"<\/a><\/p>\n

  1. See Russell Jacoby\u2019s savage review of Wright\u2019s Envisioning Real Utopias<\/i> entitled \u201cReal Men Find Real Utopias<\/a>,\u201d Dissent<\/i>, Winter 2011, for an exposure of the intellectual emptiness of a certain type of \u201ctheoretical\u201d sociology.<\/li>
  2. This argument, indeed much of the book, is anticipated not only, as it were, by common sense (most workers could tell you they don\u2019t embrace<\/i> their position but simply find it inescapable), but also by a brilliant book Chibber doesn\u2019t cite: The Dominant Ideology Thesis<\/i>, by Nicholas Abercrombie et al. (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1980). Incidentally, I myself have grappled with the question of why socialism hasn\u2019t happened yet and have offered a quite different, and perhaps more original, explanation than Chibber. See my paper “Marxism and the Solidarity Economy: Toward a New Theory of Revolution<\/a>,\u201d Class, Race and Corporate Power<\/i> 9, no. 1 (2021), as well as the shorter articles “Revolution in the Twenty-First Century: A Reconsideration of Marxism<\/a>,\u201d New Politics<\/i>, May 5, 2020; and “Eleven Theses on Socialist Revolution<\/a>,\u201d Socialist Forum<\/i> (Summer 2021).<\/p>\n

    <\/li><\/ol>The post Common Sense in the Form of Theory<\/a> first appeared on Dissident Voice<\/a>.\n

    This post was originally published on Dissident Voice<\/a>. <\/p>","protected":false},"excerpt":{"rendered":"

    In the ideological disciplines\u2014the humanities and social sciences\u2014it is rare to come across a theoretical work that doesn\u2019t seem to fetishize verbiage and jargonizing for their own sake. From the relatively lucid analytical Marxism of an Erik Olin Wright1 to the turgid cultural theory of a Stuart Hall, pretentious prolixity is, apparently, seen as an [\u2026]<\/p>\n

    The post Common Sense in the Form of Theory<\/a> first appeared on Dissident Voice<\/a>.<\/p>\n","protected":false},"author":3831,"featured_media":0,"comment_status":"closed","ping_status":"closed","sticky":false,"template":"","format":"standard","meta":{"footnotes":""},"categories":[410,469,666,250,123],"tags":[],"_links":{"self":[{"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/679332"}],"collection":[{"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts"}],"about":[{"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/types\/post"}],"author":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/users\/3831"}],"replies":[{"embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/comments?post=679332"}],"version-history":[{"count":1,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/679332\/revisions"}],"predecessor-version":[{"id":679333,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/posts\/679332\/revisions\/679333"}],"wp:attachment":[{"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/media?parent=679332"}],"wp:term":[{"taxonomy":"category","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/categories?post=679332"},{"taxonomy":"post_tag","embeddable":true,"href":"https:\/\/radiofree.asia\/wp-json\/wp\/v2\/tags?post=679332"}],"curies":[{"name":"wp","href":"https:\/\/api.w.org\/{rel}","templated":true}]}}